Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

Skip to comments.

Defense of Liberty: Freedom and War
Free Republic ^ | December 2, 2001 | Annalex

Posted on 12/02/2001 5:30:29 PM PST by annalex

Freedom and War

by Annalex

Theory of rights: an overview

Natural rights begin with the concept of bubbles of personal space that wrap each individual. Clearly, actions that do not exit the bubble do not impact similar actions of others. From this we develop a set of rightful actions as we examine each action in its immediate impact on others. If an action does not prevent others from exercising rights that we discovered so far, that action is rightful. For example, actions in defense of the personal bubble do not prevent defensive actions of others; hence self-defense is rightful. Self-amplified non-disruptive speech does not prevent self-defense and does not prevent speech of others; hence self-amplified non-disruptive speech is rightful. Voluntary exchange of property that one owns does not prevent self-defense, speech, or exchange of property by others. In this fashion, the entire set of rights can be derived inductively one by one. The common law is a practical implementation of this inductive process in historical context.

Rarely, an inaction can be violative of rights. For example, inaction next to a helpless person whose life is in an immediate peril is no different in its immediate effect from homicide if help can arrive only from the inactor. Provided that the inactor can render help without injury to himself, his inaction is unrightful, and so an act of help becomes a duty.

We note that individual can trade rights. A common example of that is commercial exchange: the buyer gives up his right to a sum of money, and the seller gives up his right to the goods sold. Business contracts involving money, labor, goods and disclosure of information are examples of complex exchange of natural rights. We can distinguish between natural rights, present as part of the natural order of the universe; and contractual rights that derive from voluntary cooperation of men.

Considerable controversy surrounds the issue of acquisition of unclaimed property. Such acquisition is competitive, so when one contender captures a particular piece of property, others are, of course, prevented from acquiring the same piece. Therefore, we can't say that the claiming of the unclaimed piece of property is necessarily rightful. We can say with certainty that if everyone interested in the property has agreed to a particular set of rules under which unclaimed property can be pursued, then to engage in pursuit of the property under such rules becomes rightful. Thus fishermen set up rules of fishing in particular waters; archeologists set up very different rules of archeological discovery. The rules reflect the nature of the property and the interests of the contenders. For example, the rules that the fishermen are likely to adopt would prohibit overfishing; in contrast to that, the search for archeological artifacts encourages complete excavation of the site. In absence of any tradition or explicit rule, the ability to physically defend the previously unclaimed property one claims amounts to the right of ownership.

We examined this definition of rights in my Mathematical Principles of Natural Rights[1], which I expanded in [2]. This article deals with one theoretical problem with the definition, and arrives to some rather unexpected applications of the theory of natural rights.

Rights in history: a dilemma

One question arises: what if the set of rightful actions depends on the order in which actions are added to the set. Imagine a core set of established rights, to which we wish to add action X and action Y. It is theoretically possible that neither X or Y present a conflict with the core, but conflict between themselves. We are faced with a paradox: if X is added first, then X appears to be rightful and Y unrightful; if Y is added first, then, vice versa, Y is rightful, but X isn't. Do such "weak" rights exist in real life?

They do. It is not difficult to find examples of two cultures, each presenting a consistent set of rights, yet the two sets are not compatible. Consider

Farmers and Indians

A sole Indian looks at the wilderness and says to himself: "I'll hunt in that forest, fish in that river, and pick berries in the bush". If several Indians arrive at the scene, they can all forage with ease and no or little rulemaking is necessary to ensure their foraging rights. Conflicts between foraging rights happen, resolved by force or negotiation. When force is resorted to, it is applied mutually, and the legal principle of foraging is not challenged: the victorious tribe simply succeeds in competitive claiming of their foraging domain. The Indian's behavior with respect to other Indians, even those he fights against, is, by and large, rightful.

When farmers homestead the wilderness, they also can rely on simple rulemaking, force, or threat of force to sort out their claims. Again, a farmer's behavior with respect to other farmers is by and large rightful: his homesteading does not prevent other homesteaders to try their luck.

The situation changes dramatically when a sole farmer and a sole Indian compete for the land. The farmer doesn't want to roam and hunt, -- his system of property rights is based on burning the forest, plowing the fields, and safeguarding the farm's perimeter. The Indian sees his system of foraging rights crumble: it is no longer the matter of not shooting someone else's goat, but the destruction of the entire foraging environment.

Although the Indians may go to war between themselves, and the farmers may fight for territory between themselves, the war between farmers and Indians is a war between civilizations. The difference is that both the farming civilization and the foraging civilization are complete and self-sufficient systems of property rights. No deal exists that would enable them to coexist and maintain their full sets of property rights. The farmers will have to become foragers, or the Indians will have to become farmers, or else the Indians have to become cocooned in what to the farming world looks like another ranch: a reservation.

Thus it is incorrect to say that property rights exist on the foundation of non-violent cooperation. They do that only within the confines of some civilizations. In other civilizations, property rights are something that is determined in a fight. Between civilizations, property rights can only exists as an outcome of a war. It is an illusion that other civilizations are simply ignorant of the only possible system of property rights that works for us. The Indian forager's property rights are just as real as the farmer's. One objective difference is that the farmer's property rights historically extend to capitalism and has brought prosperity to everyone, including the Indians on their reservations: our rights are right and their rights are wrong. Yet they are all rights, operative inside each civilization. The natural, civilization-invariant right is the right to enter competitions and act within rules mutually agreed between the competitors.

It is also incorrect to say that violence always underlies property rights. When a claim to a property is made through a show of force, the force is defensive in character, since the property was previously unowned. At the same time, the principle of non-initiation of violence, frequently used as a theoretical foundation of rights, looks insufficient to adequately explain the competitive nature of property claiming. Several distinctions in the use of violence should be made.

Gentlemen' Wars

Those occur within a given civilization; although they are violent, they are really competitive games. Farmers fighting between themselves for arable land (directly or through the proxy of professional soldiers), or hunters trying to drive off a hostile tribe understand the rules and mutually accept the violence. One relatively recent example of violent, yet civilizationally coherent system of rights is the practice of dueling. The actions the rightfullness of which is resolved through dueling seem quaint to us: nuances of etiquette, injuries to the hyper-sensitized sense of honor, sexual escapades, frat house rambunctiousness. There is little doubt that, although the violence in duels is very real, and is initiated at least by one side, the behavior is mutually agreed upon and therefore rightful as long as the rules are followed. Attempts to outlaw duels through government fiat in 17 century France were met with the same indignant protestations against tyranny that were heard a century and a half later in reference to modern civil liberties.

Another characteristic of a gentlemen's war is the honest desire to resolve a dispute where nonviolent form of argumentation failed. Each side claims to be objectively right, and, in quieter moments, would acknowledge that the other side has a plausible claim as well. Jacques Barzun describes both the legalistic and the gamelike character of medieval wars as follows [3]:

The endless local wars were not, as is believed, the doing of "robber barons": almost invariably they could show a legal right. When William the Conqueror crossed the Channel to make England his own, he had three substantial claims to the kingship. Land being the main form of wealth and the only source of a meager and chancy subsistence, owning more or less was not solely a question of pride and greed.

War, moreover, had some civilized features -- it was a game. The rules were strict. The word of honor, courtesy between foes, the captured knight deemed a 'friend and brother' until ransomed [...] -- the full code must be observed if the accusation of foul play was to be avoided. ?In 1415 the English and the French heralds watched the battle together form a high place. When the French had fled, King Henry [V] waited anxiously until the principal French herald confirmed that the English were the victors. And it was also for him to name the battle. He named it Agincourt.'"

"Gamelike" should not be taken to de-emphasize the violence. The violence in World War I, -- by the accounts of its veterans -- surpassed the brutality of World War II. However, WWI is a classic example of a gentlemen's war: it started with a formal declaration, and was greeted initially as a welcome and long-awaited resolution of conflicting national claims. It also ended formally, with bizarre attention to ceremony, Much in the Second World War resembled the pattern of the First, -- in particular, the "Strange War" period and the tales of gentlemanly sportsmanship that, we are told, existed between the English and the German pilots. I also heard a tale of a captured Soviet tank commander given by his German captors an opportunity to prove his skill in a staged tank battle, -- which he did, and was released. A theme of sportsmanship permeates the otherwise forgettable film "Enemy at the Gates", depicting a conflict between a German and a Russian snipers at Stalingrad. Yet, altogether the Second World War was a war of a different kind.

Holy Wars

... happen when two system of rights, that may be consistent in themselves, need to coexist. Either system may be incomplete, such as for example, the wholly inadequate approximations of natural rights offered by Nazi Germany or Soviet Russia. It is beside the point of this discussion to distinguish between a system of rights that is consistent with itself but not compatible with ours, and a social order that plainly doesn't acknowledge any individual rights. The important difference is that unlike a gentlemen's war, a holy war takes place between civilizations. Our Farmers and Indians example is such war. The evolving conflict between radical Islam and the Western Civilization is another.

Two recent wars provide muddled but vivid examples.

The Second World War was a reprise of WWI, and as I noted, had many features of a gentlemen's war. Yet at its core it wasn't, because neither the Western capitalism, German national socialism, or Soviet communism were compatible systems of rights. WWI could have been resolved by better diplomacy, particularly if the horror of the 4-year slaughter was somehow communicated to the politicians of August 1914. There was no peaceful resolution to Germany's or Japan's claims of civilizational superiority: if Hitler foresaw Germany's defeat he would simply have taken a longer time to prepare for the war that was integral to his worldview. Accordingly, WWII couldn't end in an armistice: a complete annihilation of the enemy's system of rights was the only possible outcome.

The Cold War, along with the Indian wars and the present day War on Terror, come the closest to a clean civilizational conflict, where each side possesses coherent and mutually exclusive ideologies. It is often thought that the Détente that preceded the collapse of Soviet communism was a compromise and a sign of the two systems converging. In fact, Détente was a way for both sides to delay their assault hoping for the other side to collapse. It is true that the West inoculated itself against the most violent and repugnant forms of communism by taking on elements of socialism -- elements that by now have taken a life of their own and may still destroy the Western civilization from within. Nevertheless no convergence of communism and the Western civilization is really possible, because communism is incompatible with natural rights, of which the West is the keeper, on any level. The present coexistence of socialist democratic government and individualist humanist culture in North America and in Europe is unstable and headed for collapse, just like the Cold War could only end with a collapse of the USSR.

Because of the incompatible (or non-existent) system of rights on the other side, each side views the enemy as not fully human. This is not merely a result of wartime propaganda. Rights to a human are inseparable from his physical existence. The absence of rights breeds cripples. The sullen masses of Soviet factory workers or Chinese peasants marching without protest from one site of national sacrifice to another did not look human to a Westerner. Conversely, a freely traveling, self-sovereign, opinionated, self-motivated Westerner didn't look real, or human, to an obedient, collective-aware Homo Sovieticus.

A common mistake is to treat a holy war as a gentlemen's war. This mistake is often committed by peacemakers. In a gentlemen's war a truce is a way to prevent the conflict from undesirable escalation; a truce may evolve into a lasting peace. In a holy war no peace is possible; a truce allows the weaker side to regroup and resume the fight, when the only way to peace is through its complete defeat. The entire knot of Middle Eastern policy since Camp David is the sorry result of this mistake.

Just Wars

Are there any rules that control warmaking under natural law? The question is trivial in the case of competitive violence with mutually agreed upon rules between individuals. Clearly, the presence of rules makes the violence generally rightful for both sides. In a conflict between individuals in absence of rules, the answer is equally obvious: initiated violence is unrightful; reactive violence in proportion to the initiated violence is rightful. However, the paradox of the situation is that when, like in a holy war, each side attempts to complete its culturally circumscribed system of rights, each side views its actions as rightful: the farmer is convinced that burning the forest for agriculture is rightful because he only interacts with other farmers and their rights don't suffer, and the Indian believes that foraging across cultivated fields is rightful because no other Indian is prevented from doing the same. Thus, although both sides violate the natural law, neither side would be able to admit it, and both sides would fight to the bitter end.

The analysis gets complicated when instead of conflicts between individuals we have a conflict between managed collectives, -- that is, between nations ruled by their governments. The determinative factors then become, in addition to the question of initiation of violence versus reactive violence, whether the government is properly representing its constituents, and whether the violence involves noncombatants.

A short digression is necessary at this point. We consider a government representative when a mechanism exists for the citizens to alter the foreign policy. Typically, elections are such mechanism. A representative government can be assumed to have a broad mandate to wage a war under some constitutional conditions. At every given moment in time, a sizable percent of the citizenry may disagree with their government's foreign policy. However, for our purposes in this article it is sufficient to assume that the nation's citizens have universally agreed to delegate their collective defense to the government even when they disagree with a particular policy. Such delegation occurs in any modern democratically governed country, even though any democratic country we know is otherwise not wholly respectful of natural rights due to the pervasiveness of statism in its domestic political organization [4].

A war of aggression may be just even though individual acts of aggression are always unrightful, in one case (discovered by Ayn Rand in [5]). If a representative government sees a national interest being served by attacking a dictatorial government, and can do so without incurring a significant overall cost, it can initiate aggression against such government, as long as the civilian population of the dictatorship does not suffer beyond measure and its liberation is among the war's intended outcomes. Indeed, the population of the country being attacked is already suffering from the political violence initiated by the dictator; the effect on the population is the relief from oppression, bought at the price of limited wartime hardship. The overall costs of war to the aggressor are outweighed by the national interest served; while the cost to the aggressor's combatants may be their life, in a representative government consent of the soldier to go to battle can be presumed. In short, a free nation may invade an enslaved nation if it wishes, as long as the aggression is limited against that nation's government.

While individual response to an aggression or a credible threat thereof is rightful as long as it is proportional to the injury, a reactive war may still be unjust. Let us consider four possibilities: a reactive war waged by a representative government, and a reactive war waged by a government that usurps power, in combination with the independent cases of hostilities that spare non-combatants or victimize noncombatants.

1. A representative government waging a reactive war strictly against enemy soldiers is obviously rightful. The only difference between such war and the case of individual self-defense is that the defense is delegated to the professional army.

2. A representative government waging a reactive war that victimizes enemy civilians is just only if the victimized civilians are directly in charge of their military. That is because if a strong agency relationship exists between a certain segment of the enemy populace and the enemy military, then that civilian segment is the initiator of violence. Note that the mere fact that the enemy's government is democratically elected is not enough to indict the entire population, because military policy even in a democracy cannot be conducted with universal consent. In practical terms it means that things like assassinations of enemy leaders are permissible in an otherwise just war.

3. A dictatorial government waging a reactive war strictly against enemy soldiers may still be an unjust war. That is because in absence of the delegation of defense the individual rights test comes down to whether a particular segment of civilian population is directly attacked. Imagine a country with an oppressed minority inside, which is being invaded. The civilian population in the invader's path is under direct threat and no delegation of defense is required to make its defense by the professional military (or, to that matter, by anyone else) rightful. However, the oppressed minority may in fact welcome the invasion. If the defensive military action is undertaken on the minority's territory, its justice becomes very problematic. Such was the situation when some oppressed minorities in Stalin's Soviet Union welcomed the invading German army, seeing in Hitler a liberator.

4. A dictatorial government waging a reactive war that victimizes enemy civilians may be acting unjustly even in strikes against the enemy's civilian leaders. That is for the same reasons as strikes against the enemy's military in the previous case.

As we've seen, strikes against civilians are nearly always unjust. However, in the context of an overall just war, tactical strikes against civilian population are permissible whenever the enemy forces mingle with it. In such case, the victimization is initiated by the enemy's soldiers who, in effect, take civilians as hostages. The combatants on the just side may strike at civilians as long as the primary target is the enemy combatants. The difference between this situation and a criminal hostage crisis being resolved by police is that the police has a contractual responsibility to protect the hostage, and the soldier's don't have any special responsibilities toward the enemy's civilians.

The Church, in particular St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas developed the ethics of just war in the Christian West as part of natural law [6,7]. While no reference to individual rights was made, their conclusions, based on the common sense of right and wrong, match the above analysis very well. As we've seen, a just war must aim to remedy a wrong, must employ force in proportion to the goal of just peace, must be conducted by a just government and must minimize civilian suffering. Analytical approaches available under the theory on individual natural rights allowed us to refine those general principles, and in some occasions, reach conclusions that startle the conventional wisdom. Let us briefly comment on the elements of the Christian theory of just war.

Just authority: Only the legitimate rulers of the state may declare war.

As we've seen, a government that lacks authorization from its populace may wage a war only inasmuch as it happens to coincide with the just intentions of the populace.

Just cause: A nation may wage war on another nation only if the latter has done some injury.

Indeed, a just war, even when aggressive, is against a government that had violated individual rights.

Right intentions: The intention of the warriors must be the achievement of just peace.

A war has its justification in violations of individual rights. As soon as the violation is remedied (to the extent the war is capable of delivering a remedy), the war must end.

Proportionality: The anticipated good must not be outweighed by the bad likely to be caused along the way.

This principle applies to the conduct of the war, as well as to its declaration. In either case, it is a cardinal principle of individual rights. Since a war is a collective enterprise, we need to consider the situation when the retaliation that would be properly directed at X causes harm to Y -- in other words, when a war harms the innocent. The justification of such harm is, as we've seen, in that the innocent is in effect taken hostage by the guilty party. But then the harm to the hostage needs to be weighed against the likely harm to future victims. If a thief who stole $100 is surrounded by a SWAT team and takes a hostage, the SWAT team should let the thief go because the likely future harm -- another stolen $100 -- is less than the likely harm to the hostage if the thief is apprehended violently.

Probability of success: There must be a reasonable prospect that the war will succeed.

This is where individual rights differ from the justice of the collective enterprise. For an individual, it is rightful to engage in desperate self-defense. It is however not rightful for the government to wage a war whose likely outcome to its citizens will worsen their present condition.

Last resort: Peaceful alternatives must all have been exhausted first.

This principle was implicitly used by Aquinas in arguing for the sovereign authority, when he noted that anyone ranking below the sovereign can use courts and not violence. With the emergence of transnational jurisdictions, this principle becomes independent form the Just Authority principle. Indeed, if a peaceful resolution is possible and war is waged instead, then that war is by definition aggressive. We saw that an aggressive war is still justified under some conditions if it serves the national interest. It is difficult to imagine a scenario when a peaceful resolution would not serve the national interest just as well or better than hostilities.

Discrimination. No killing of noncombatants.

We saw that noncombatants are just targets in two cases: when they directly authorize unjust violence, and when they are collaterally victimized as a result of mingling with the militants. This is how the principle of discrimination is traditionally applied as well, although the US law has a somewhat strange prohibition on assassination of foreign leaders.

Conclusions.

It is incorrect to view natural rights as an antithesis to violence. While unprovoked and unexpected assault is certainly unrightful, many forms of violence are a necessary component of natural rights. The principle of non-initiation of violence, usually equated with natural rights, is not particularly helpful in addressing real life conflicts where the act of initiation could be traced back centuries, or where initiation is mutual. The proper approach to conflicts is to examine the cultural aspect of the violence, rather than "who started it". Especially important is to distinguish between cases when the violence is mutually agreed upon, -- and therefore by and large rightful even for the side that makes the first move, -- and cases when no mutual agreement is possible. The latter is a kind of conflict that allows for only radical resolutions, and an attempt to deescalate the conflict through coercive peacemaking only prolongs the violence.

The precise analysis of individual rights can be applied to complex relationships between the citizens, their governments and their military, that are typical in wars. The traditional in the Christian West concept of just war is in compliance with the theory of individual natural rights. In particular, St. Aquinas' requirement of "authority of the sovereign" -- in modern parlance, representative government -- is pivotal in determining the scope of just military actions.

Notes

[1] The Mathematical Principles of Natural Rights

[2] The Mathematical Principles of Natural Rights (With Addenda)

[3] "From Dawn to Decadence", pp. 226-227, embedded quote from John Keegan, "The Face of Battle", italics are Barzun's.

[4] This point is argued in Foreign Policy and Natural Law.

[5] Ayn Rand. Collectivized Rights. (Also see Just Intervention.

[6] Whether it is always sinful to wage war? (Aquinas on Just War)

[7] Just War Theory

All rights reserved. Reproduction in full is authorized with attribution to the Free Republic and Annalex.



TOPICS: Constitution/Conservatism; Editorial
KEYWORDS: libertarians
Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-2021-4041-6061-65 next last
To: Demidog
Thus any suggestion that bin Laden's declaration of war puts us at war is false. We are not at war either as our leaders have not declared a constitutional war.

If what you say is true -- and it's not -- then your words "constitutional war" is a redundancy.

41 posted on 12/03/2001 7:29:04 PM PST by FreeReign
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 16 | View Replies]

To: FreeReign
What I say is true. We are not at war. There is no declaration of war at all. Your president is using dictatorial powers.
42 posted on 12/03/2001 7:36:13 PM PST by Demidog
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 41 | View Replies]

To: Demidog
If the victim of a crime can empower his government to go after the perpetrator, then the perpetrator can empower his government to protect his rights.

The perpetrator is not acting rightfully. He may have some mechanical means to compel the government, but if he succeeds, the government actions on his behalf won't be rightful, -- it will be an extension of his crime or a hostage to it. "Empowering" or "powers" as the word is used in the US Constitution connotes a relationship of rightful agency, and that is how I use it.

43 posted on 12/03/2001 7:56:39 PM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 39 | View Replies]

To: Free the USA
The calculation is more apt to be investing $500 dollars in a rifle to dispatch the wolf verses $1,000 for the fence.

Why? That would be a cost and benefit analysis, not rights analysis. Besides my actions of shooting the wolf would be rightful or unrightful regardless of whether I have to buy a rifle. The proper rights analysis is to compare the costs of the two violations of rights. The wolf owner violates my rights at the price of the fence. I violate his rights at the price of the wolf. Of course, there are intangibles that I purposely excluded, reducing pet ownership to mere money, etc.

Libertarianism is a theory more than it is a casuistry. In theory we deal with hundred dollar wolves. In casuistry we deal with the recent helicopter attack on Arafat's headquarters. One can't understand the latter without the former.

44 posted on 12/03/2001 8:10:23 PM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 40 | View Replies]

To: annalex
The perpetrator is not acting rightfully.

Says who? The prosector must present enough credible evidence to show that he's a legitimate suspect. The prosecutor(The U.S.) must respect the soverignty of the nation just as he must respect the soverignty of any home in America. He cannot enter without enough evidence to convince a judge that he has a resonable belief that he has the right person.

He may not kill the family for demanding that the evidence be presented, nor may the government prosecute a war killing the man's countrymen without due process.

By bombing and killing Afghanis other than bin Laden, we are unjustly denying them due process. That is as far from libertarian as it gets and I am disgusted that you want to justify such behavior.

45 posted on 12/03/2001 8:22:48 PM PST by Demidog
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 43 | View Replies]

To: annalex
Suicide, although sinful, is generally a right.

I thought I recall you attributing the source of natural rights to God...:)

But anyways, we hold in abeyance the rights of children to vote, drink etc. b/c they're not rationally fit to do so, and likewise with criminals and the insane. I guess the point boils down to, can someone who wishes to kill themselves be thought rationally competent to decide such a thing? Of course, this brings up the interesting point of dying for one's country, which I would also be interested in hearing your thoughts about, given that we are only obligated to save someone if it places us in no danger--or are there special wartime clauses in individualism?

46 posted on 12/03/2001 9:03:10 PM PST by Pistias
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 34 | View Replies]

To: annalex
Those agreed upon rules are internationally recognized norms of conflict resolution, but the militant Islamic civilization organically cannot abide by them and retain its identity.

Q: If one's culture (or one's regime) is threatened with extinction or a change that would be equivalent to it, would one be justified in breaking "rules of conduct?" Likewise, what are two incompatible cultures to do if there are no rules of conduct in place?

47 posted on 12/03/2001 9:06:49 PM PST by Pistias
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 35 | View Replies]

To: Demidog
Says who?

Says Reason. Your post, when it talks of prosecutors presenting evidence, commits the fallacy of placing jurisprudence before the natural law. The reverse is true: natural rights exist regardless of the judicial superstructure to enforce them. When the matter falls outside of a single jurisdiction, as is the case with any war, the justice of the war would depend on the tenets of the natural law as we interpret it in our minds.

In this task, bin Laden's case presents no difficulty unless you warp the matter with enough pointless references to "sovereignty". Bin Laden caused a massacre to happen and he took the country og Afghanistan hostage so that he and his leutenants escape justice. Individuals who are victimized by that and fear another attack (which bin Laden promised on television) deputized the US military to destroy his network. When civilians are placed, or place themselves in the way of our retaliation, which is directed at Al Qaeda, they will be harmed. We have just cause, just "sovereign" (government) and just methods.

48 posted on 12/04/2001 6:38:28 AM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 45 | View Replies]

To: Pistias
Rights do come from God, but so do all things. Rights and righteousness are two different things.

Children and other incompetents do have the same natural rights, but they are not capable of evaluating them, so that job is delegated to adults. A suicide is rightful if it harms no others in comparison to the pain to self the suicide seeks to stop. Its rightfullness is independent from the suicidal man's ability to evaluate it.

Symmetrically, acts of valor should not be confused with duty. The duty to rescue appears when the injury to the resucer is negligible, but it is valorous to come to the rescue selflessly.

A dying culture gains no extra "rights". Thus, the dying Arab Warrior culture, by rights, is not entitled to go out and bomb buildings, but they would be wholly justified to confine their struggle to the cultural or economic sphere. I suggest they breed horses and start martial art studios.

49 posted on 12/04/2001 6:50:59 AM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 46 | View Replies]

To: annalex
You assume that there is reasonable evidence and that it is just to kill civilians in Afghanistan for their refusal to turn him over.

You still haven't shown that there is evidence which warrants these actions. A white paper by Tony Blair who does not have the U.S. best interests at heart (nor the constitution) is not sufficient.

Where's the beef? They won't even show the American people this evidence. That in itself makes it suspect apart from the fact that they won't declare war. They can't because Afghanistan hasn't done anything to the U.S. which warrants a war.

50 posted on 12/04/2001 7:00:38 AM PST by Demidog
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 48 | View Replies]

To: annalex
A suicide is rightful if it harms no others in comparison to the pain to self the suicide seeks to stop

Nice in practice, but we're still faced with the fact that 9 out of 10 suicides would have to be thought of as not capable of evaluating the rightfulness of their suicide...though I'm sure one could argue reasonably for elderly/terminal assisted suicide on your grounds (which, by the way, happens nearly every day where a relative o' mine works via morphine). Still,

Its rightfullness is independent from the suicidal man's ability to evaluate it

You got that right.

The duty to rescue appears when the injury to the resucer is negligible, but it is valorous to come to the rescue selflessly

I suppose we can't prudently expect people to be heroes, but I just can't get this quote out of my head reading your treatment of valor:

"No matter whether a man is highborn or low, if he has not put his life on the line at least once he has cause for shame." --Nabeshima Naoshige, Ideals of the Samurai

they would be wholly justified to confine their struggle to the cultural or economic sphere

Here's something I never understood about the Lockean system, I'd be grateful if you'd explain it to me: these guys didn't agree to play by any rules, so why is it "unrightful" for them to use any means necessary if they're going to die? No deal exists that would enable them to coexist and maintain their full sets of...rights...other civilizations, property rights are something that is determined in a fight.

I suggest they breed horses and start martial art studios.

If I had the loot and the land, that's what I'd be doing right now (along with FReeping and philosophizing, of course).

51 posted on 12/04/2001 8:17:13 AM PST by Pistias
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 49 | View Replies]

To: Pistias
Nice in practice

Er...make that theory.

52 posted on 12/04/2001 8:18:35 AM PST by Pistias
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 51 | View Replies]

To: Demidog
You assume that there is reasonable evidence and that it is just to kill civilians in Afghanistan for their refusal to turn him over.

I may assume that the intelligence evidence is compelling without being shown it, but I understand that it can't be released to the general public. It has been released to the British, hence the significance of the British government and not ours publishing the White Paper. I know that it is just to kill civilians in Afghanistan under the circumstances explained in the article.

Here are the preface and the conclusion of the White Paper; the entire text is here: RESPONSIBILITY FOR THE TERRORIST ATROCITIES IN THE UNITED STATES, 11 SEPTEMBER 2001 - AN UPDATED ACCOUNT.

This document does not purport to provide a prosecutable case against Usama Bin Laden in a court of law. Intelligence often cannot be used evidentially, due both to the strict rules of admissibility and to the need to protect the safety of sources. But on the basis of all the information available HMG is confident of its conclusions as expressed in this document.

RESPONSIBILITY FOR THE TERRORIST ATROCITIES IN THE UNITED STATES, 11 SEPTEMBER 2001 - AN UPDATED ACCOUNT

INTRODUCTION

1. The clear conclusions reached by the government are:

2. The material in respect of 1998 and the USS Cole comes from indictments and intelligence sources. The material in respect of 11 September comes from intelligence and the criminal investigation to date. The details of some aspects cannot be given, but the facts are clear from the intelligence.

3. The document does not contain the totality of the material known to HMG, given the continuing and absolute need to protect intelligence sources.

[...]

Conclusion

74. The attacks of the 11 September 2001 were planned and carried out by Al Qaida, an organisation whose head is Usama Bin Laden. That organisation has the will, and the resources, to execute further attacks of similar scale. Both the United States and its close allies are targets for such attacks. The attack could not have occurred without the alliance between the Taleban and Usama Bin Laden, which allowed Bin Laden to operate freely in Afghanistan, promoting, planning and executing terrorist activity.

While not sufficient as a prosecutorial case (for same imaginary world government jurisdiction), it meets the standard of reasonableness, necessary to show just cause.

53 posted on 12/04/2001 8:29:37 AM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 50 | View Replies]

To: Pistias
why is it "unrightful" for them to use any means necessary if they're going to die?

I thought we were talking of a dying culture, not a dying human being. That is when I said that the dying Arab Warrior culture, which bin Laden defends, would rightly defend itself with economic or cultural means. If they were threatened physically, then it would have been rightful for them to respond physically, provided the codicils of just war are satisfied. As it stands, the Twin Tower massacre and the bombings in Israel violated every single one of them.

54 posted on 12/04/2001 11:24:10 AM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 51 | View Replies]

To: annalex
It lists no evidence. It merely states that the U.S. government reached a conclusion. And I do not accept this conclusion without something more concrete. I notice that our government is indiscriminately shutting down internet access and money transfer capabilities of those who have absolutely no relationship in fact to Al Quada or bin Laden.

I know that it is just to kill civilians in Afghanistan under the circumstances explained in the article.

No you don't. Civilians are not responsible for what a Saudi National planned while inside their borders (if in fact he really did).

55 posted on 12/04/2001 1:09:45 PM PST by Demidog
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 53 | View Replies]

To: Demidog
It lists no evidence.

From the White Paper:

62. From intelligence sources, the following facts have been established subsequent to 11 September; for intelligence reasons, the names of associates, though known, are not given.

Civilians are not responsible

Some are and some, perhaps, most, are not. Quoting myself:

As we've seen, strikes against civilians are nearly always unjust. However, in the context of an overall just war, tactical strikes against civilian population are permissible whenever the enemy forces mingle with it. In such case, the victimization is initiated by the enemy's soldiers who, in effect, take civilians as hostages. The combatants on the just side may strike at civilians as long as the primary target is the enemy combatants. The difference between this situation and a criminal hostage crisis being resolved by police is that the police has a contractual responsibility to protect the hostage, and the soldier's don't have any special responsibilities toward the enemy's civilians.

56 posted on 12/04/2001 1:49:09 PM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 55 | View Replies]

To: annalex
Nothing is specific and it is extremely convenient for the government to claim that they can't show anyone the evidence.

Not good enough in my book. Certainly not good enough to deny Afghan civilians their right to due process.

57 posted on 12/04/2001 2:04:41 PM PST by Demidog
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 56 | View Replies]

To: Demidog
It's as specific as they can make it without compromising the intelligence sources. Again, you are forgetting that it is not a court of law, and that it is the Al Qaeda and the Taliban who are victimizing the civilians. If there were a court of law, they would have the burden of proof, but then that court of law would have the ability to shield the intelligence sources from the general public. As it is, we have not a court trial but a war. Our government is entitled by the Constitution to not make any legal case at all, go to war based on undisclosed intelligence, then face the elections. Then the justice of this war would forever be an academic exercise to decipher. As it is now, with the information they chose to disclose, a plausible case can be made for the just cause, but an element of trust in the doings of this government is needed. It is theoretically possible that in fact the US and the Israeli government hijacked those planes in order to start a war, an the US government ordered the CIA to produce fake evidence and show that to the British. This sounds like your operative theory.
58 posted on 12/04/2001 2:54:10 PM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 57 | View Replies]

Comment #59 Removed by Moderator

To: Okiegolddust
Here's to your health and welcome.
60 posted on 12/11/2001 1:03:53 PM PST by annalex
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 59 | View Replies]


Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-2021-4041-6061-65 next last

Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.

Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

FreeRepublic, LLC, PO BOX 9771, FRESNO, CA 93794
FreeRepublic.com is powered by software copyright 2000-2008 John Robinson