Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

Skip to comments.

The right has f****ed up minds: Meet the researcher who terrifies GOP Congress[political psychology]
Salon ^ | March 5, 2015 | Paul Rosenberg

Posted on 03/06/2015 1:47:36 AM PST by Cincinatus' Wife

In the immediate aftermath of World War II, a wide range of thinkers, both secular and religious, struggled to make sense of the profound evil of war, particularly Nazi Germany and the Holocaust. One such effort, “The Authoritarian Personality” by Theodore Adorno and three co-authors, opened up a whole new field of political psychology—initially a small niche within the broader field of social psychology—which developed fitfully over the years, but became an increasingly robust subject area in 1980s and 90s, fleshing out a number of distinct areas of cognitive processing in which liberals and conservatives differed from one another. Liberal/conservative differences were not the sole concern of this field, but they did appear repeatedly across a growing range of different sorts of measures, including the inclination to justify the existing social order, whatever it might be, an insight developed by John Jost, starting in the 1990s, under the rubric of “system justification theory.”

The field of political psychology gained increased visibility in the 2000s as conservative Republicans controlled the White House and Congress simultaneously for the first time since the Great Depression, and took the nation in an increasingly divisive direction. Most notably, John Dean’s 2006 bestseller, “Conservatives Without Conscience,” popularized two of the more striking developments of the 1980s and 90s, the constructs of rightwing authoritarianism and social dominance orientation. A few years before that, a purely academic paper, “Political Conservatism as Motivated Social Cognition,” by Jost and three other prominent researchers in the field, caused a brief spasm of political reaction which led some in Congress to talk of defunding the entire field.

But as the Bush era ended, and Barack Obama’s rhetoric of transcending right/left differences captured the national imagination, an echo of sentiment appeared in the field of political psychology as well. Known as “moral foundations theory,” and most closely associated with psychologist Jonathan Haidt, and popularized in his book “The Righteous Mind,” it argued that a too-narrow focus on concerns of fairness and care/harm avoidance had diminished researchers’ appreciation for the full range of moral concerns, especially a particular subset of distinct concerns which conservatives appear to value more than liberals do. In order to restore balance to the field, researchers must broaden their horizons—and even, Haidt argued, engage in affirmative action to recruit conservatives into the field of political psychology. This was, in effect, an argument invoking liberal values—fairness, inclusion, openness to new ideas, etc.—and using them to criticize or even attack what was characterized as a liberal orthodoxy, or even a church-like, close-minded tribal moral community.

Yet, to some, these arguments seemed to gloss over, or even just outright dismiss a wide body of data, not dogma, from decades of previous research. While people were willing to consider new information, and new perspectives, there was a reluctance to throw out the baby with the bathwater, as it were. In the most nitty-gritty sense, the question came down to this: Was the rhetorical framing of the moral foundations argument actually congruent with the detailed empirical findings in the field? Or did it serve more to blur important distinctions that were solidly grounded in rigorous observation?

Recently, a number of studies have raised questions about moral foundations theory in precisely these terms—are the moral foundations more congenial to conservatives actually reflective of non-moral or even immoral tendencies which have already been extensively studied? Late last year, a paper co-authored by Jost—“Another Look At Moral Foundations Theory”—built on these earlier studies to make the strongest case yet along these lines. To gain a better understanding of the field as a whole, moral foundations theory as a challenge within it, the problems that theory is now confronting, and what sort of resolution—and new frontiers—may lie ahead for the field, Salon spoke with John Jost. In the end, he suggested, moral foundations theory and system justification theory may end up looking surpsingly similar to one another, rather than being radically at odds.

You’re most known for your work developing system justification theory, followed by your broader work on developing an integrated account of political ideology. You recently co-authored a paper “Another Look at Moral Foundations Theory,” which I want to focus on, but in order to do so coherently, I thought it best to begin by first asking you about your own work, and that of others you’ve helped integrate, before turning to moral foundations theory generally, and this critical paper in particular.

So, with that in mind as a game plan, could you briefly explain what system justification theory is all about, how it was that you became interested in the subject matter, and why others should be interested in it as well.

When I was a graduate student in social psychology at Yale back in the 1990’s I began to wonder about a set of seemingly unrelated phenomena that were all counterintuitive in some way and in need of explanation. So I asked: Why do people stay in abusive relationships, why do women feel that they are entitled to lower salaries than men, and why do African American children come to think that white dolls are more attractive and desirable? Why do people blame victims of injustice and why do victims of injustice sometimes blame themselves? Why is it so difficult for unions and other organizations to get people to stand up for themselves, and why do we find personal and social change to be so difficult, even painful? Of course, not everyone exhibits these patterns of behavior at all times, but many people do, and it seemed to me that these phenomena were not well explained by existing theories in social science.

And so it occurred to me that there might be a common denominator—at the level of social psychology—in these seemingly disparate situations. Perhaps human beings are in some fairly subtle way prone to accept, defend, justify, and rationalize existing social arrangements and to resist attempts to change the status quo, however well-meaning those attempts may be. In other words, we may be motivated, to varying degrees, to justify the social systems on which we depend, to see them as relatively good, fair, legitimate, desirable, and so on.

This did not strike me as implausible, given that social psychologists had already demonstrated that we are often motivated to defend and justify ourselves and the social groups to which we belong. Most of us believe that we are better drivers than the average person and more fair, too, and many of us believe that our schools or sports teams or companies are better than their rivals and competitors. Why should we not also want to believe that the social, economic, and political institutions that are familiar to us are, all things considered, better than the alternatives? To believe otherwise is at least somewhat painful, insofar it would force us to confront the possibility that our lives and those of others around us may be subject to capriciousness, exploitation, discrimination, injustice, and that things could be different, better—but they are not.

In 2003, a paper you co-authored, “Political Conservatism as Motivated Social Cognition” caused quite a stir politically—there were even brief rumblings in Congress to cut off all research funding, not just for you, but for an entire broad field of research, though you managed to quell those rumblings in a subsequent Washington Post op-ed. That paper might well be called the tip of the iceberg of a whole body of work you’ve helped draw together, and continued to work on since then. So, first of all, what was that paper about?

We wanted to understand the relationship, if any, between psychological conservatism—the mental forces that contribute to resistance to change—and political conservatism as an ideology or a social movement. My colleagues and I conducted a quantitative, meta-analytic review of nearly fifty years of research conducted in 12 different countries and involving over 22,000 research participants or individual cases. We found 88 studies that had investigated correlations between personality characteristics and various psychological needs, motives, and tendencies, on one hand, and political attitudes and opinions, on the other.

And what did it show?

We found pretty clear and consistent correlations between psychological motives to reduce and manage uncertainty and threat—as measured with standard psychometric scales used to gauge personal needs for order, structure, and closure, intolerance of ambiguity, cognitive simplicity vs. complexity, death anxiety, perceptions of a dangerous world, etc.—and identification with and endorsement of politically conservative (vs. liberal) opinions, leaders, parties, and policies.

How did politicians misunderstand the paper, and how did you respond?

I suspect that there were some honest misunderstandings as well as some other kinds. One issue is that many people seem to assume that whatever psychologists are studying must be considered (by the researchers, at least) as abnormal or pathological. But that is simply untrue. Social, cognitive, developmental, personality, and political psychologists are all far more likely to study attitudes and behaviors that are normal, ordinary, and mundane. We are primarily interested in understanding the dynamics of everyday life. In any case, none of the variables that my colleagues and I investigated had anything to do with psychopathology; we were looking at variability in normal ranges within the population and whether specific psychological characteristics were correlated with political opinions. We tried to point some of these things out, encouraging people to read beyond the title, and emphasizing that there are advantages as well as disadvantages to being high vs. low on the need for cognitive closure, cognitive complexity, sensitivity to threat, and so on.

How has that paper been built on since?

I am gratified and amazed at how many research teams all over the world have taken our ideas and refined, extended, and otherwise built upon them over the last decade. To begin with, a number of studies have confirmed that political conservatism and right-wing orientation are associated with various measures of system justification. And public opinion research involving nationally representative samples from all over the world establishes that the two core value dimensions that we proposed to separate the right from the left—traditionalism (or resistance to change) and acceptance of inequality—are indeed correlated with one another, and they are generally (but not always) associated with system justification, conservatism, and right-wing orientation.

Since 2003, numerous studies have replicated the correlations we observed between epistemic motives, including personal needs for order, structure, and closure and resistance to change, acceptance of inequality, system justification, conservatism, and right-wing orientation. Several find that liberals score higher than conservatives on the need for cognition, which captures the individual’s chronic tendency to enjoy effortful forms of thinking. This finding is potentially important because individuals who score lower on the need for cognition favor quick, intuitive, heuristic processing of new information, whereas those who score higher are more likely to engage in more elaborate, systematic processing (what Daniel Kahneman refers to as System 1 and System 2 thinking, respectively). The relationship between epistemic motivation and political orientation has also been explored in research on nonverbal behavior and neurocognitive structure and functioning.

Various labs have also replicated the correlations we observed between existential motives, including attention and sensitivity to dangerous and threatening stimuli, and resistance to change, acceptance of inequality, and conservatism. Ingenious experiments have demonstrated that temporary activation of epistemic needs to reduce uncertainty or to attain a sense of control or closure increases the appeal of system justification, conservatism, and right-wing orientation. Experiments have demonstrated that temporary activation of existential needs to manage threat and anxiety likewise increases the appeal of system justification, conservatism, and right-wing orientation, all other things being equal. These experiments are especially valuable because they identify causal relationships between psychological motives and political orientation.

Progress has also been made in understanding connections between personality characteristics and political orientation. In terms of “Big Five” personality traits, studies involving students and nationally representative samples of adults tell exactly the same story: Openness to new experiences is positively associated with a liberal orientation, whereas Conscientiousness (especially the need for order) is positively associated with conservative orientation. In a few longitudinal studies, childhood measures of intolerance of ambiguity, uncertainty, and complexity as well as sensitivity to fear, threat, and danger have been found to predict conservative orientation later in life. Finally, we have observed that throughout North America and Western Europe, conservatives report being happier and more satisfied than liberals, and this difference is partially (but not completely) explained by system justification and the acceptance of inequality as legitimate. As we suspected many years ago, there appears to be an emotional or hedonic cost to seeing the system as unjust and in need of significant change.

“Moral foundations theory” has gotten a lot of popular press, as well as serious attention in the research community, but for those not familiar with it, could you give us a brief description, and then say something about why it is problematic on its face (particularly in light of the research discussed above)?

The basic idea is that there are five or six innate (evolutionarily prepared) bases for human “moral” judgment and behavior, namely fairness (which moral foundations theorists understand largely in terms of reciprocity), avoidance of harm, ingroup loyalty, obedience to authority, and the enforcement of purity standards. My main problem is that sometimes moral foundations theorists write descriptively as if these are purely subjective considerations—that people think and act as if morality requires us to obey authority, be loyal to the group, and so on. I have no problem with that descriptive claim—although this is surely only a small subset of the things that people might think are morally relevant—as long as we acknowledge that people could be wrong when they think and act as if these are inherently moral considerations.

At other times, however, moral foundations theorists write prescriptively, as if these “foundations” should be given equal weight, objectively speaking, that all of them should be considered virtues, and that anyone who rejects any of them is ignoring an important part of what it means to be a moral human being. I and others have pointed out that many of the worst atrocities in human history have been committed not merely in the name of group loyalty, obedience to authority, and the enforcement of purity standards, but because of a faithful application of these principles. For 24 centuries, Western philosophers have concluded that treating people fairly and minimizing harm should, when it comes to morality, trump group loyalty, deference to authority, and purification. In many cases, behaving ethically requires impartiality and disobedience and the overcoming of gut-level reactions that may lead us toward nepotism, deference, and acting on the basis of disgust and other emotional intuitions. It may be difficult to overcome these things, but isn’t this what morality requires of us?

There have been a number of initial critical studies published, which you cite in this new paper. What have they shown?

Part of the problem is that moral foundations theorists framed their work, for rhetorical purposes, in strong contrast to other research in social and political psychology, including work that I’ve been associated with. But this was unnecessary from the start and, in retrospect, entirely misleading. They basically said: “Past work suggests that conservatism is motivated by psychological needs to reduce uncertainty and threat and that it is associated with authoritarianism and social dominance, but we say that it is motivated by genuinely moral—not immoral or amoral—concerns for group loyalty, obedience to authority, and purity.” This has turned out to be a false juxtaposition on many levels.

First researchers in England and the Netherlands demonstrated that threat sensitivity is in fact associated with group loyalty, obedience to authority, and purity. For instance, perceptions of a dangerous world predict the endorsement of these three values, but not the endorsement of fairness or harm avoidance. Second, a few research teams in the U.S. and New Zealand discovered that authoritarianism and social dominance orientation were positively associated with the moral valuation of ingroup, authority, and purity but not with the valuation of fairness and avoidance of harm. Psychologically speaking, the three so-called “binding foundations” look quite different from the two more humanistic ones.

What haven’t these earlier studies tackled that you wanted to address? And why was this important?

These other studies suggested that there was a reasonably close connection between authoritarianism and the endorsement of ingroup, authority, and purity concerns, but they did not investigate the possibility that individual differences in authoritarianism and social dominance orientation could explain, in a statistical sense, why conservatives value ingroup, authority, and purity significantly more than liberals do and—just as important, but often glossed over in the literature on moral foundations theory—why liberals value fairness and the avoidance of harm significantly more than conservatives do.

How did you go about tackling these unanswered questions? What did you find and how did it compare with what you might have expected?

There was a graduate student named Matthew Kugler (who was then studying at Princeton) who attended a friendly debate about moral foundations theory that I participated in and, after hearing my remarks, decided to see whether the differences between liberals and conservatives in terms of moral intuitions would disappear after statistically adjusting for authoritarianism and social dominance orientation. He conducted a few studies and found that it did, and then he contacted me, and we ended up collaborating on this research, collecting additional data using newer measures developed by moral foundations theorists as well as measures of outgroup hostility.

What does it mean for moral foundations theory?

To me, it means that scholars may need to clean up some of the conceptual confusion in this area of moral psychology, and researchers need to face up to the fact that some moral intuitions (things that people may think are morally relevant and may use as a basis for judging others) may lead people to behave in an unethical, discriminatory manner. But we need behavioral research, such as studies of actual discrimination, to see if this is actually the case. So far the evidence is mainly circumstantial.

And what future research is to come along these lines from you?

One of my students decided to investigate the relationship between system justification and its motivational antecedents, on one hand, and the endorsement of moral foundations, on the other. This work also suggests that the rhetorical contrast between moral foundations theory and other research in social psychology was exaggerated. We are finding that, of the variables we have included, empathy is the best psychological predictor of endorsing fairness and the avoidance of harm as moral concerns, whereas the endorsement of group loyalty, obedience to authority, and purity concerns is indeed linked to epistemic motives to reduce uncertainty (such as the need for cognitive closure) and existential motives to reduce threat (such as death anxiety) and to system justification in the economic domain. So, at a descriptive level, moral foundations theory is entirely consistent with system justification theory.

Finally, I’ve only asked some selective questions, and I’d like to conclude by asking what I always ask in interviews like this—What’s the most important question that I didn’t ask? And what’s the answer to it?

Do I think that social science can help to address some of the problems we face as a society? Yes, I am holding out hope that it can, at least in the long run, and hoping that our leaders will come to realize this eventually.

Our conversation leads me to want to add one more question. Haidt’s basic argument could be characterized as a combination of anthropology–look at all the “moral principles” different cultures have advanced—and the broad equation of morality with the restraint of individual self-interest and/or desire. Your paper, bringing to attention the roles of SDO and RWA, throws into sharp relief a key problem with such a formulation—one that Southern elites have understood for centuries: wholly legitimate individual self-interest (and even morality—adequately feeding & providing a decent future for one’s children, for example) can be easily over-ridden by appeals to heinous “moral concerns”, such as “racial purity”, or more broadly, upholding the “God-given racial order.”

Yet, Haidt does seem to have an important point that individualist moral concern leave something unsaid about the value of the social dimension of human experience, which earlier moral traditions have addressed. Do you see any way forward toward developing a more nuanced account of morality that benefits from the criticism that harm-avoidance and fairness may be too narrow a foundation without embracing the sorts of problematic alternatives put forward so far?

Yes, and there is long tradition of theory and research on social justice—going all the way back to Aristotle—that involves a rich, complex, nuanced analysis of ethical dilemmas that goes well beyond the assumption that fairness is simply about positive and negative reciprocity.

Without question, we are a social species with relational needs and dependencies, and how we treat other people is fundamental to human life, especially when it comes to our capacity for cooperation and social organization. When we are not engaging in some form of rationalization, there are clearly recognizable standards of procedural justice, distributive justice, interactional justice, and so on. Even within the domain of distributive justice—which has to do with the allocation of benefits and burdens in society—there are distinct principles of equity, equality, and need, and in some situations these principles may be in conflict or contradiction.

How to reconcile or integrate these various principles in theory and practice is no simple matter, and this, it seems to me, is what we should focus on working out. We should also focus on solving other dilemmas, such as how to integrate utilitarian, deontological, virtue-theoretical, and social contractualist forms of moral reasoning, because each of these—in my view—has some legitimate claim on our attention as moral agents.


TOPICS: Crime/Corruption; Culture/Society; Editorial; Government
KEYWORDS: jonathanhaidt; morality; politics; psychology; socialscience; sociology
Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-2021-4041-6061-8081-91 next last
To: antidisestablishment
...Strange that conservatives are judged as authoritarian, and yet it's the left who consistently impose their totalitarian sociology by force.

They're a sick bunch that use slight of hand.

61 posted on 03/06/2015 5:27:23 AM PST by Cincinatus' Wife
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 58 | View Replies]

To: fieldmarshaldj

Again! Why are we not up to our keisters in omelettes, with all the eggs being broken?


62 posted on 03/06/2015 5:27:59 AM PST by gogeo (If you are Tea Party, the eGOP does not want you.)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 14 | View Replies]

To: Excellence

srbfl


63 posted on 03/06/2015 5:28:05 AM PST by Excellence (Marine mom since April 11, 2014)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: UnbelievingScumOnTheOtherSide

That seems more than a little bit hysterical and smug at the same time. Care to discuss?


64 posted on 03/06/2015 5:30:21 AM PST by gogeo (If you are Tea Party, the eGOP does not want you.)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 15 | View Replies]

To: Cincinatus' Wife
This pansy should spend some time listening to Bill Whittle,a guy who's done a better job of educating *me* in the realities of everyday life *and* political philosophy than just about anyone else.A seven minute long video by him has more wisdom and logic than any 100,000 word long piece of drivel that this punk can produce.
65 posted on 03/06/2015 5:31:39 AM PST by Gay State Conservative (Obama;A Low Grade Intellect With Even Lower Morals)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Blue Collar Christian
This stuff gives me a headache Mrs. Cinci.

They use that against you.

66 posted on 03/06/2015 5:34:21 AM PST by gogeo (If you are Tea Party, the eGOP does not want you.)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 32 | View Replies]

To: exDemMom

Equality (as defined by the left) is the antithesis of Liberty. If these values are understood as the foundation of the political poles, the problem becomes clear:

You cannot institute liberty though authoritarian measures.

Equality,on the other hand...


67 posted on 03/06/2015 5:36:26 AM PST by antidisestablishment (Inaction at this point is not capitulation, itÂ’s cooperation. GOP delenda est!)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 37 | View Replies]

To: gogeo

>That seems more than a little bit hysterical and smug at the same time. Care to discuss?

Sure, which would you like?

War on Drugs - Controlled Substances Act upheld by the Supreme Court on the basis of Wickard v Filburn (1942) that bastardized the Interstate Commerce Clause into anything that “affects” commerce. Also makes possible EPA, OSHA, Endangered Species Act etc. Similar control of substances under the progressive 1906 Pure Food & Drug Act was limited by the court, requiring a constitutional amendment for alcohol in intrastate commerce in wet states.

anti-gambling laws, anti-prostitution laws - Abridgement of contracts in violation of Art. I sec. 10 of the Constitution for purely religious reasons in violation of the 1st Amendment. Yes, they dress it up in the language of harm being done to willing participants - the very essence of tyranny.

“Of all tyrannies, a tyranny sincerely exercised for the good of its victims may be the most oppressive. It would be better to live under robber barons than under omnipotent moral busybodies. The robber baron’s cruelty may sometimes sleep, his cupidity may at some point be satiated; but those who torment us for our own good will torment us without end for they do so with the approval of their own conscience. They may be more likely to go to Heaven yet at the same time likelier to make a Hell of earth. This very kindness stings with intolerable insult. To be “cured” against one’s will and cured of states which we may not regard as disease is to be put on a level of those who have not yet reached the age of reason or those who never will; to be classed with infants, imbeciles, and domestic animals.”

C.S. Lewis, God in the Dock: Essays on Theology (Making of Modern Theology)

FCC regulations - “Congress shall make no law...abridging the freedom of speech...” Of course, “freedom of speech” does not include anything we don’t like, which changes over time.

Any of these or something else?


68 posted on 03/06/2015 6:09:47 AM PST by UnbelievingScumOnTheOtherSide (ISLAM DELENDA EST)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 64 | View Replies]

To: Cincinatus' Wife

I would offer in contrast Michael Savage’s book “Liberalism is a mental disorder”.


69 posted on 03/06/2015 6:18:51 AM PST by tbw2
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: John S Mosby

The only somewhat reliable and believable studies on differences in political philosophy I would agree on are the MRI studies showing liberals are much harder to disgust than conservatives, and that liberals in general have a much higher novelty seeking behavior (hence loving the new).


70 posted on 03/06/2015 6:20:28 AM PST by tbw2
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 10 | View Replies]

To: Yardstick

Michael Savage’s “Liberalism is a mental disorder”.


71 posted on 03/06/2015 6:21:03 AM PST by tbw2
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 40 | View Replies]

To: Cincinatus' Wife

Related note - the Soviets didn’t label everyone a dissident and send them to the camps. They also diagnosed many political dissidents as having “sluggish schizophrenia”. You couldn’t see that you lived in paradise and the freest society, you must be crazy; here is the mental asylum and drugs until you agree with that official reality.


72 posted on 03/06/2015 6:23:20 AM PST by tbw2
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 9 | View Replies]

To: driftless2

Liberals are the fascists they accuse conservatives of being.


73 posted on 03/06/2015 6:24:12 AM PST by tbw2
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 41 | View Replies]

To: driftless2

I gave it a try, about four paragraphs, and then skimmed over the rest. Complete nonsense. I am sure Dwight Eisenhower took all this into consideration as he planned the D-Day invasion. And Ronald Reagan stared at his naval daily over these concepts. And Obama trembles as he writes his executive orders.


74 posted on 03/06/2015 6:40:11 AM PST by odawg
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 39 | View Replies]

To: tbw2

The problem, in addition to not being a science, is that this “scientist” starts with a premise and proceeds to supply the “proof”.

Among others, the problem is also THEIR definition of a conservative. True conservatives entertain all KINDS of change, embrace it within the freedom of conservative thought. What these morons are talking about is a close minded person, of whom there is a great abundance among lockstep liberal and RINO big government statists. Because statism demands NO CHANGE, status quo and power that is doled out to the “worthy” apparatchiks and only them.

True conservatives, intellectually run circles around this kind of behaviour and are.. truly... free.


75 posted on 03/06/2015 7:02:30 AM PST by John S Mosby (Sic Semper Tyrannis)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 70 | View Replies]

To: Cincinatus' Wife

In the fourth paragraph is “not dogma”.

The “science” of Psychology is dogma, particularly political psychology.


76 posted on 03/06/2015 7:32:15 AM PST by X-spurt (CRUZ missile - armed and ready.)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: RginTN

Wrong people in charge of the right idea.


77 posted on 03/06/2015 7:34:13 AM PST by MrB (The difference between a Humanist and a Satanist - the latter admits whom he's working for)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 6 | View Replies]

To: odawg
This screed goes back to the "conservatives are crazy" "arguments" liberals have used since I was a teen fifty years ago. I was once a liberal, and I know how they think. They simply can't believe anybody could have any objections to the growth of the huge mega-state.

That's why basically they never really get around to honestly debating conservative points. They avoid honest arguments by claiming conservatives are deranged...or racist, sexist, homophobic...you know the drill. To get a liberal to actually sit down and talk about the problem of the growth of government is well nigh impossible.

I started turning conservative back in the sixties and seventies watching W.F. Buckley's "Firing Line" on PBS. Buckley put forth a lot of arguments that found me in agreement with. That's when I started wondering if I was really a liberal.

And that's what conservatives should do with liberals. It might feel good to call libs names, but I'd rather challenge them and make them reconsider what they think is the truth.

78 posted on 03/06/2015 8:36:04 AM PST by driftless2 (For long term happiness, learn how to play the accordion.)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 74 | View Replies]

To: Cincinatus' Wife

Professing themselves to be wise, they became fools, (Romans 1:22)

Ever learning, and never able to come to the knowledge of the truth. (2 Timothy 3:7)

Rather than the speculation of carnally minded men, the liberal ethos flows from the original “share the wealth” scheme was that was behind the devil’s occupy movement, asserting, “I will ascend into heaven, I will exalt my throne above the stars of God...I will be like the most High,” (Is. 14:13,14) as the original liberal elite who judged himself fit to reign, selfishly seeking climbing up an unlawful way to power.

And then basically told Eve that she was victimized by an oppressive God who would not share His deity with her due to His one rule, and thus she was just in her rebellion. (Gn. 3)

And being frustrated in his lust for power, the devil seeks worship thru proxy servants, establishing an alternative world thru servants who gain power by fostering the victim-entitlement mentality, that those who earned a higher standard of living are their enemies, and thus the liberal elites present themselves as saviors of the oppressed.

But having gained the power they selfishly seek, they reign as kings, and slowly bring all into dependance upon them so that all serve them, so that the end is worse than any oppression the people originally realized.


79 posted on 03/06/2015 9:20:23 AM PST by daniel1212 (Come to the Lord Jesus as a contrite damned+destitute sinner, trust Him to save you, then live 4 Him)
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]

To: Cincinatus' Wife

...and the left is irremediably psychotic.

IMHO


80 posted on 03/06/2015 9:34:07 AM PST by ripley
[ Post Reply | Private Reply | To 1 | View Replies]


Navigation: use the links below to view more comments.
first previous 1-2021-4041-6061-8081-91 next last

Disclaimer: Opinions posted on Free Republic are those of the individual posters and do not necessarily represent the opinion of Free Republic or its management. All materials posted herein are protected by copyright law and the exemption for fair use of copyrighted works.

Free Republic
Browse · Search
News/Activism
Topics · Post Article

FreeRepublic, LLC, PO BOX 9771, FRESNO, CA 93794
FreeRepublic.com is powered by software copyright 2000-2008 John Robinson